Wednesday, May 8, 2013

Sources of Values

  Once again I've found myself trying to decode a philosophical writing, this time an article in The New York Review of Books, excerpted from Ronald Dworkin's forthcoming book Religion Without God.  It has more than a touch of metaphysics, so I probably wouldn't have finished reading it had I not been spurred on by my cousin G.  He is ever so much more into philosophy than I.

  Dworkin makes a case, already appreciated by some religions of the East but not sufficiently in the West, that being religious doesn't require belief in a deity.  He starts by defining "religious attitude"—in essence the conjoining of awe at the beauty of the universe with a faith that an objective set of values exists.  (As we shall see, the crux of this definition is the word objective.)  To Dworkin, being religious simply means having such a religious attitude, which can be theistic or atheistic.

  Abrahamic theists, for example, may be awed by God's creation of the cosmos from the void; atheists may be awed by creation from the Big Bang.  Theists might believe that cruelty is wrong because God says so from on high; atheists because they "cannot [have a conviction that cruelty is really wrong] without thinking that it is objectively true."  (There's circular reasoning here, which Dworkin later defends—see below.)  In thus virtually equating the nature of religious attitudes that theists and atheists may have, Dworkin makes the inclusion of God by the former and not the latter seem of little import.  History, of course, says otherwise. 

  Let's leave that contentious issue aside and go to the crux: the meaning of "objectivity." By objective values, Dworkin has in mind Platonic ideals that are independent of the mundane world.  They may be endowed by a transcendental deity; but he denies that they can originate from naturalism—the belief "that nothing is real except what can be studied by the natural sciences."  Values, he maintains, "are real and fundamental … as real as trees and pain," and there is no way of discovering them by naturalistic inquiry.

  In thus rejecting naturalism, Dworkin a priori takes evolution out of the picture as a source of values.  He says, "Suppose we find undeniable evidence that we hold the moral convictions we do only because they were evolutionarily adaptive, which certainly did not require them to be true.  Then, in this view, we would have no reason to think that cruelty is really wrong."  (My italics, emphasizing Dworkin's insistence that objective moral truth cannot be grounded in natural inquiry.) 

  Instead, Dworkin relies on "ungrounded realism" to be in touch with moral truth.  He says that "the world of value is self-contained and self-certifying," which we accept as a matter of faith.  He admits to circularity here, but claims it is not much different from physical science, which ultimately depends on faith in assumptions such as causation.  "In each domain we accept felt, inescapable conviction rather than the benediction of some independent means of verification as the final arbiter of what we are entitled responsibly to believe."  (This is a misleading comparison, because scientific assumptions are always tentative and subject to invalidation; Dworkin's objective values, being self-certifying, are not.)

  Dworkin is of course entitled to define "religious attitude" as he wishes, including a definition that excludes naturalists from being capable of it.  Yet, materialist that I am and philosopher that I am not, I don't understand why he would insist on doing so.  Why can it not be that cruelty is considered wrong just because it tends to be deselected by the evolutionary process?  Recall from E. O. Wilson's book The Social Conquest of the Earth, which I discussed in a previous posting, the contention that human evolution proceeds by competition among groups as well as among individuals, the former trumping the latter in conformity with an "iron rule": selfish individuals beat altruistic ones, yet groups of altruists beat groups of selfish individuals.  According to Wilson, different groups choose different sets of values with which to compete.  Some values, however, have become universal among groups and societies at large, which is not evidence that they are transcendentally objective truths, only that they have become pragmatically necessary for the competitive survival of a society in a given era. 

  A core set of universally accepted values therefore might well have arisen through the evolutionary process.  Philosopher Philip Kitcher, in his book The Ethical Project, looks on this evolution as a collective enterprise taken on by the species over tens of thousands of years as it sought ways to live successfully in larger and larger groups.  In this light, for example, the natural rights proclaimed during the Enlightenment are not a human discernment of objective values "endowed by their Creator"; rather they represent a stage in the evolution of values achieved by humankind during the 17th and 18th centuries.

  My response to Dworkin's article is twofold.  First, I think he has unnecessarily conflated two concepts: "religion," which in both common parlance and Dworkin's lexicon has preternatural elements; and "religious attitude," which—despite Dworkin's strange definition of it—need not have that tinge.  A naturalist, following Einstein, can have a religious attitude by simply being in awe of the sublimity of the universe, without also subscribing to a preternaturalness of values.

  Second, while again I am assuredly no philosopher, in my estimation a blending of Dworkin's and Kitcher's value constructs is possible, by replacing objectivity with universality.  Instead of demanding that values be "self-contained and self-certifying," beyond human jurisdiction, think of them as continuing reformulations by the species itself, under evolutionary pressure as it climbed out of savagery.  As Wilson points out, for example, proscription of incest is now universal among societies, initially dating well into pre-historic times.  Proscription of murder is more recent, dating at least to the Judaic commandment.  Proscriptions of slavery and cruelty are very much more recent still.  In this merged construct, Dworkin's "felt, inescapable conviction" that these values are true would itself stem from the same evolutionary forces as the values themselves.

  Thus, one can conceive of quasi-objective (in the sense of universal) core values that are evolutionarily modified with time.  As with objective values, they are ideals that humanity strives for in a given era, usually without total success.  They are the forward-looking what-should-be of value as opposed to what-is.  They are the substance of Kitcher's ethical project, which—as he points out—is a work in progress.  

  I'll end by apologizing for what may appear an unseemly posthumous quarrel with Professor Dworkin.  (Sadly, he died in February prior to the publication of both his NYRB article and the book from which it was drawn.)  He was an eminent philosopher and scholar of law, and I am a less than a novice in both those fields.  Yet I feel that a response to him is warranted from a materialist, someone whose awe at the universe's majesty is matched with a belief in evolutionarily rather than preternaturally derived values.